If quantum mechanics or other fundamental theories of physics have it that small physical entities which make up everything else do not behave deterministically, does that indeterminism inherited by all other larger entities, whether those are molecules, gases, instantiated computer programs, and people? In general, does indetermism on one "lower" physical level imply indetermism on a "higher" one?

The answer to the general question is that indeterminism at the "lower" level doesn't have to mean indeterminism at "higher" levels. Here's an abstract way to think about it. Suppose some theory has a set of possible states -- call it S -- and a strict deterministic law governing how the states change over time. Let's suppose that this theory is both true and know to be true. But suppose, unbeknownst to us, each of the states in S can be realized in many different ways, at some sub-microscopic level that we don't have access to. And suppose that even though the law that tells us how we get from one state in S to another is deterministic, there's no deterministic law governing exactlywhich way states in S will be realized as the system moves from one state to another.We might never have any reason to believe any such thing, but it could be true all the same. That's one story about how indeterminism at the micro level might not infect the macro level. Another way is a "for all practical...

Setting aside worries about quantum mechanics, would it be possible for there to be a plank of wood which is an irrational number (say, pi) of feet in length?

Sure. For one thing, nature doesn't care about our arbitrary units. Suppose we have a plank of wood that''s exactly a foot long. Now I define a new unit: a schfoot. Anything one foot long is exactly pi schfeet long. Is there any mystery about things being pi schfeet long? Also -- since we're setting aside issues about quanta and, I assume, the possibility that space is granular, can't we make sense of something changing length continuously? A twig that's a foot long and growing will pass through an uncountable number of irrational lengths on its way from being a foot long to being two feet long.

This is a moral question that came to my mind after some reading of law books, but please take it only as a moral question. Suppose that Mary lent me 100 euros. When the time came that I should pay her back, I didn't do it, although I had the money (I preferred to spend it somewhere else). A friend of ours, Pete, knowing what had happened, gave Mary 100 euros saying that he was paying my debt. She accepted the money from him, and Pete told me what he did. What is my moral duty now? Should I give 100 euros to Mary? Do I still owe her 100 euros? Or do I owe Pete 100 euros, although he acted without my consent?

I'm inclined to make a distinction between two things here: the grammar, as it were, of the word "owe" and the right thing to do. I think a case can be made for saying that since you weren't a party to Pete's deed and didn't consent to it, then you owe Mary 100 euros, in at least one recognizable sense of "owe." And one can also make the case that you don't "owe" Pete 100 euros, since you didn't enter into any arrangement with him. I'm pretty sure that if we were in the realm of contract law (suppose there actually is a signed note here), this is how it would sort out, though there might be some tricky legal issues that, as an amateur, I'm overlooking. That said, if I were advising someone in this position, I'd say that at the least, they should pay Pete back. It would be a good thing as well to come clean to Mary. But whatever one thinks the moral obligations are here, we can prise them apart -- to at least some degree -- from strictly legal issue about who owes what to whom.
Law

Dred Scot v. Stanford, Supreme Court rules slavery is constitutional. Plessy v. Ferguson, Supreme Court rules segregation is constitutional. Today they’ve allowed the government to spy on its own citizens. They’ve outlawed partial birth abortion. They’ve pursued pro-torture policies. The Supreme Court is appointed, not elected. I was never given any say in WHO gets to be a Justice. While the President is only allowed a max of eight years in office, and legislators have to repeatedly struggle for re-election…the justices serve for life and there’s no way for us to remove them from office. …Considering that they’re the ones who get to decide what the constitution means, (Mauburry v. Madison, Judicial Review) don’t you think this seems a bit out of place in the American government? I mean…they tell us what our constitution means, and there’s nobody to check it. Seems tyrannical, primitive, undemocratic, and out of place in an republic government to me.

Of course, if you vote, you do get at least an indirect say in who's on the court. And after all, your say in a good many matters is only indirect. In any case, if the question is what the Constitution means, there's something unappetizing about having the check be one that's too directly tied to the political realm. Constitutions are supposed to set some things beyond the reach of the ordinary democratic process, not least so as to evade what some call the "tyranny of the majority." But in any case, it's not as though there are no counterweights. Some have held that Congress has the authority to declare that some matters are simply outside the purview of the Court, though I gather that this is controversial. But if the Court makes a constitution ruling that enough people object to, the Constitution can be amended, and has been many times. More generally, what strikes me (as someone born elsewhere) is that far from being "primitive," the American system of checks and balances - including...

As my class and I were examining the implications of ethical egoism, a dilemma became apparent to me. How could a superogatory act exist to an ethical egoist? If one is only moral by pursuing their best self-interest, how could one go above and beyond that which is already best? (I see that this question could be viewed as a violation of guidelines, but if the honor code is accepted here, I can assure you that this is not a class question. Just personal curiosity.)

What strikes me first is that ethical egoism isn't the real issue here. If any ethical theory claims that we're obliged to maximize something or other, then there's no room left for supererogation. This means that the same point would apply, e.g., to certain forms of utilitarianism. As you are in effect pointing out, nothing's better than the best. But the second point is that one could be an ethical egoist (or a utilitarian, for that matter) and not think that one is always obliged to maximize one's self-interest. One might think, for example, that some sort of "satisficing" is good enough to discharge one's duties. In other words, there would be a standard of what's good enough, and meeting that would suffice for doing what one ought to. But that leaves room for supererogation.

Having grown tired of reading secondary material in my study of philosophy, I have decided to read primary texts in a chronological, rather than thematic, order. I have started with Plato and have read most of the works I can find online or at my library. Before I move on to Aristotle, I would like your advice. Do you think a chronological approach is a good idea for someone untrained in philosophy? Do you think I should read every work by a given philosopher, or are there 'key' works that serve as their primary contribution to the field? If the latter, are there any lists that you are aware of that state what those key works are?

Consider an analogy. Suppose I wanted to learn physics, and I decided to read great works of physics in chronological order. Whatever value that project might have, it would be a poor way to become a physicist. So no: I wouldn't recommend reading historical works in chronological order. I wouldn't even recommend putting a lot of emphasis on reading historical works, period. One reason: philosophy is essentially something you do . Working philosophers aren't intellectual historians. They're trying to sort their way through problems. Work by older philosophers can be suggestive and relevant, but most working philosophers spend very little of their time reading the classics. I'm guessing that by "secondary sources" you mean commentaries on historical works or introductory material on various problems. My suggestion: move next to edited collections of contemporary papers on problems that you're interested in. For example: if you're interested in the free will problem, you might consider getting...

I'm trying to wrap my mind around the Reformed Epistemology idea of the proof of God, but I am a total novice at this and I can't figure it out. As far as I can tell by the article "Without Evidence or Argument" by Kelly James Clark, the proof is 1) We should believe that God exists only with sufficient proof that God exists 2) We cannot get sufficient proof that God exists, because every argument would have to be justified by another argument infinitely Therefore, we do not need proof that God exists. I am completely baffled by this, and I'm pretty sure I'm reading it all wrong. I could really use a hand. Am I even understanding the premises at all?

Reformed epistemologists, as I understand them, are saying that we could know that God exists even if we were utterly unable to give a proof. That's because on their view, knowing something isn't a matter of being able to give reasons for believing it. Knowing something is a matter of being connected to it in the right sort of way. A little too simply, suppose there really is a God, and that the reason I believe God exists is because God reliably causes me to believe it. (And if God's causings wouldn't be reliable, then which ones would?) Reformed epistemologists would say that in that case, I know that God exists. This isn't a proof that God exists, and it isn't an argument to convince you that you should believe in God. It's a special case of a general view about knowledge: that we know things when they're true and our beliefs about them are caused in the right sort of way. And notice that this sort of view has some advantages. If there really is a computer in front of me, and if my belief...

I'm in a rather unique conundrum. After much reading, listening and reflection I've concluded that there is no source of moral good or evil beyond that which serves mankind's survival. That is, one's loyalty to country and family are only meaningful in as much as they can be rationalized as serving this ultimate purpose. The result is that I now find myself at odds with what most people here in the USA and most of the world consider to be the foundation of stability -- that is religion. It's not that I'm an atheist and belief there is no God -- or even that one cannot know whether God exists. I consider myself to be an agnostic, which I define as having no belief on the matter but as having an open mind about it. Unfortunately I've seen more credible evidence for ancient astronauts than for a God. Both are intriguing notions but I can't base moral decisions on them. This leaves me with the problem of feeling quite separate from everyone I know and love. I'm aware of the historical role of religion as a...

You've put your conclusion by saying that morality is entirely a matter of what promotes human survival, but that, I'd suggest, isn't really the issue. I'm assuming you might be open to the idea that rampant cruelty to animals is wrong, whether or not it harms the chances for human survival. But even if you agreed, that wouldn't get you out of the dilemma you feel you're faced with. The real issue, I think, is that you've become convinced that morality doesn't need religion, and most of the people around you think otherwise. But here's a little secret: even people who think that there's an intimate connection between religion and morality ignore the connection in most of their moral thinking. There are very few people who think that murder would be perfectly acceptable except that God has commanded otherwise. There are very few people who think it would be okay to steal someone's wallet but for the fact that God disapproves. The fact is that aside from a few hot-button issues (abortion and...

When did the definitions of induction and deduction change from reasoning from the universal to the particular (deduction) and particular to universal (induction), to this non-distinction of the strength of support the premises give to the conclusion? When did it happen and who did it?

I did it, last Tuesday. But actually, I'm a bit puzzled. The distinction between deduction and induction never was a distinction between universal-to-particular and particular-to-universal. Consider: All dogs are mammals; all mammals are animals. So all dogs are animals. We haven't gone from universal to particular, but surely the reasoning is deductive. Or better: If Max is in Cincinnati, then so is Jennifer. But Max is in Cincinnati. So Jennifer is there too. A perfectly good deduction, but not a case of reasoning from universal to particular. On the induction side, suppose that every egg I've eaten has given me hearburn. I'm about to eat an egg. So I infer that this particular egg will (probably) give me heartburn. This is inductive reasoning, but it doesn't go from particular to universal. In a correct deductive argument, the conclusion follows from the premises. Put roughly, it's impossible for the premises to be true and the conclusion simultaneously false, but whether premises or...

For what I've seen until now, logical laws are always assumed to be necessarily true (in the "all possible worlds" sense), but is it possible that this necessity is weaker? Is it possible that our logical capabilities are adaptations to physical regularities of the actual world and are still evolving, together with our minds? If our logical capabilities are tracking our evolution, then the Necessity of Logic laws could be only Physical, instead of Metaphysical, and there could be possible worlds where the Physics would constrain Logic differently. This (I think) would also have implications regarding the Ontological commitment of Logic: instead of assuming that there is none, it would be possible, even likely, that the physical existents of the World would appear in our logical theories. Has anyone put forward sustained arguments for/against this?

People have talked about this. One oft-cited paper is Hilary Putnam's 1968 paper "Is Logic Empirical?" (Reprinted in his Mathematics, Matter and Method as "The Logic of Quantum Mechanics.") Putnam's arguments were of a "web of belief" sort: our beliefs form a web with some more central than others, but all are revisable. Quantum mechanics, Putnam thought, has given us the same sorts of reasons to revise our logical opinions as relativity gave us to revise our geometrical opinions. A large literature (to which I made some contributions) followed in the wake of Putnam's paper. The issues here resist easy summary. In an unpublished talk, Saul Kripke offered some trenchant criticisms of Putnam's approach. My own view is that many of Kripke's criticisms can be met, but the upshot is not exactly that logic is empirical in the way Putnam believed. Rather, it could be, for all Kripke has shown, that there are logical relations found in some worlds that may be absent in others. If that's right, it...

Pages