Our panel of 91 professional philosophers has responded to

124
 questions about 
Profession
43
 questions about 
Color
392
 questions about 
Religion
117
 questions about 
Children
68
 questions about 
Happiness
221
 questions about 
Value
75
 questions about 
Perception
134
 questions about 
Love
23
 questions about 
History
96
 questions about 
Time
5
 questions about 
Euthanasia
151
 questions about 
Existence
154
 questions about 
Sex
105
 questions about 
Art
284
 questions about 
Mind
208
 questions about 
Science
36
 questions about 
Literature
1280
 questions about 
Ethics
110
 questions about 
Biology
89
 questions about 
Law
70
 questions about 
Truth
69
 questions about 
Business
374
 questions about 
Logic
75
 questions about 
Beauty
88
 questions about 
Physics
31
 questions about 
Space
2
 questions about 
Action
67
 questions about 
Feminism
58
 questions about 
Abortion
218
 questions about 
Education
51
 questions about 
War
58
 questions about 
Punishment
32
 questions about 
Sport
24
 questions about 
Suicide
27
 questions about 
Gender
80
 questions about 
Death
54
 questions about 
Medicine
574
 questions about 
Philosophy
77
 questions about 
Emotion
287
 questions about 
Language
170
 questions about 
Freedom
81
 questions about 
Identity
282
 questions about 
Knowledge
244
 questions about 
Justice
110
 questions about 
Animals
39
 questions about 
Race
2
 questions about 
Culture
4
 questions about 
Economics
34
 questions about 
Music

Question of the Day

You ask: "morally speaking, can my action BE more serious or offensive only because other people see it so?

Suppose there was someone weird enough to think that your sleeping man would be indifferent between having his feet used to prop a window open and being raped in his sleep. And to make things clearer, suppose this person thinks that the sleeping man wouldn't mind either. It's hard to imagine the psychology of such a person, and may not even be clear if he would be a competent moral agent, but set that aside. What should we say?

Perhaps we would say that we shouldn't judge this person more harshly for doing one of these things rather than the other. No harm was meant; it's just that the person was massively, unimaginably clueless. This would be someone we should keep close watch over; if they actually carried out the rape, we would be fully justified in confining them in some way. We might abstain from moral judgments about the person himself, but there's another question we can ask: if the sleeping man was raped, is what happened to him worse than it would have been if he'd merely had his feet used as a window-stick?

It's a pretty safe bet that he would think so, and that matters. In fact it matters a lot. We don't count up harm or moral offense solely in the coin of bruises. A morally competent person knows that if someone would strongly prefer not to be treated in a certain way, that is, as far as it goes, a reason not to do it; not an all-things-considered reason, of course, but a reason that normally deserves to be taken into account. Indeed: if there's no weighty reason to ignore the person's strong preference, it will normally count as a decisive reason not to do so.

Why? I suppose a certain crude form of utilitarianism might make that look like a good question, though if it came to it it wouldn't be hard to conjure up consequentialist reasons not to rape sleeping people (let alone people who aren't asleep.) But set that aside. Part of what morality demands of us is that we respect the dignity of other people, and that we not treat them simply as means. Using someone's feet as a window stick without their consent is not a way to respect their dignity, and amounts to using them as a mere means, but raping them while asleep is so much further along both scales that to most people it will feel like a whole different kind of offense. To say that most people could be wrong about this would require a very special story to be believable. The example you've given doesn't promise one.

What makes things offensive is, no surprise, closely tied to what people find offensive. What makes something a violation is—again, no surprise, closely tied to what people would see as a violation if it happened to them. The link isn't inviolable, but it's not accidental either. It's difficult to make sense of the claim that something is not actually a violation or an offense even if most thoughtful, informed people would see it as such.

Now of course we sometimes work our way to moral insights that we once were blind to. Understanding the deep wrongness of slavery, for example, is such a case. This happens when people learn to see things that they had overlooked or ignored or turned away from. It's typically a matter of coming to see something from another's point of view. But that is exactly what's missing in the example you offer. In effect, we're asked to ignore the point of view of the person whose point of view seems prima facie most relevant.